2018年4月30日月曜日

トランプ、墓穴を掘るの話



イメージ 1



トランプ、墓穴を掘るの話

一昨日のFox News の朝の番組で、トランプはあることないこと、ないことあることをいろいろとわめきちらしたが、一番本人にとって致命的なことがある。マイケル・コーンとの関係を可能な限り抹殺しようとする発言が1つ。下記の記事にもあるように、ナショナル・インクワイラーというタブロイド -トランプのいいなりの雑誌 - が、コーンを明確に批判する記事をトップに掲げている。だが、この行動はトランプにとって致命的になる可能性がある -アヴェナッティがそう言っている。というのは、コーンは10数年間にわたり、トランプの暗い国際取引を一手に引き受けてきたフィクサーであり、その事務所、宿泊ホテル、自宅が、FBIのニューヨーク南部支部により家宅捜索を受け、大量の資料が押収されたこと、そしてそのなかには、ストーミーがコーエンとのあいだで結んだNDAと交換に13万ドルが支払われたことに関する資料が含まれている可能性が大であるからである。
 トランプの失言は、コーンは自分にとっては、ほんのささいな位置しか占めていない、と述べた後、「ストーミーの件でコーンが自分の弁護をしているにすぎない」と述べたことである。つまり、これまでの知らぬ存ぜずの立場から一転、この裁判については、コーンが自分の弁護に立っている、と明確に述べた点である。
 
 このDNAの存在は1月にWAPOがすっぱ抜いたことで知られるようになった。それは、
コーンとダニエルズとのあいだで、10年前の件について秘密を守る、という条件のもとで13万ドルが支払われたというものである。ここで”DD” という人物が登場してきているが、この人物の欄はブランクになったままである。
 じつは、DDはトランプの変名であることが確実視されている(ほかにあり得ない)。
この書類がすっぱぬかれて以来、コーンは、「自分の一存で行ったこと。13万ドルは自分がもつ不動産を担保に用立てたが、トランプはまったくこのことを知らない」と述べ続けてきた。こんな話、素人でも信じるはずのない類のものである。弁護士が顧客との相談なしに、しかも自分の家を担保に資金を用立てるなどといったことは、あってはならない行為である。
 トランプは1週間前までは、この用立てについても、知らぬ存ぜずで述べてきていたが、この電話インタビューで、怒りに任せて、ストーミーのこの裁判ではコーンが弁護活動をしていることを認める発言をしてしまった、ということである。

 このことで、トランプ側は、押収された資料をFB I側が読む権利を禁止するということができなくなった。中立の立場の人物により、どう扱うかが今後決定されることになったが、トランプは、コーンとの関係をきわめて小さなものと述べたことで、押収資料の大半はFBIが自由に読める、そしてその中にはストーミーのこの契約書も、さらには同様のNDAが少なくとも10種類あると言われているものも、検察側が証拠資料として持ち出すことができる状況が確定したということになる。

 さらに致命的なのは、コーンが完全に四面楚歌的に追い込まれてしまったという現実である。コーンは「トランプ命」的に活動してきていたが、そしてそのため、彼は、トランプ政権内で要職につけるとおもっていたのが、裏切られた、にもかかわらず、忠誠を誓って行動してきたが、ここにきて、完全にトカゲのしっぽ切り扱いを受けることになった。トランプの任命はきまぐれで、そのため、内閣はほとんど本来の機能を果たすことができないままで今日に至っている。
 こうなると、コーンがトランプに忠誠を尽くす理由は何も存在しなくなる。というのは、このまま進行するとかれは、確実に長期の懲役刑を宣告されるからである。そしてそのことにより得るものは何もない。「転べば」大幅な減刑が得られる。そして検察側は、もちろん一次証言によりトランプの国際舞台、モスクワやウクライナなどなどでの暗いビジネス活動の実態告白を得ることができることになる。
 アヴェナッティは、きわめて雄弁で自信に満ちている。一介の弁護士がポルノ女優の弁護を引き受けたということから始まったこの話は、いまやトランプ大統領を追い落とす最有力の一翼に躍り出る、という考えられない方向への展開 -これは特別検察官ミュラーの場合とはまったく性質の異なる環境である - に向かっている。
 現在の共和党、とくにその指導部の基礎理念を放棄して、トランプの言いなりになっている状況下にあってアヴェナッティとストーミーの活動 -ストーミーがポルノ女優であるという経験が、ここにきて通常の女性では耐えられないようなプレッシャーに打ち勝つという強みを与えている - が、大きな注目を浴びている。

(アヴェナッティの話はきわめて論理的である。そして非常に自信をもって活動していることがうかがわれる。トランプは、口から出まかせでしゃべり、そして話すごとにウソが入っているのだが、彼は一度も前言の失言を訂正したことがない。こうした人間があいかわらず発言を許され続けているということ自体、大統領職のもつ問題にも行きあたっている。1年4カ月、毎日この状態が続いている。日本の政治家の場合であれば、1度の失言でも命取りになるが、トランプはいまだにホラを吹き続け、気に入らないと罵声を浴びせ続けている。ツイッターで。
 トランプの情報源で、笑えないような本当の話がある。トランプはテレビを長時間、とくにお気に入りのフォックス・ニュースを聞き続け、そこから得た話を、早朝のツイッターですぐにオウムのように使っていることが知られている。実際、そっくりそのままの表現がツイートされている様子が、他の番組ではよく登場して語られている。こういう人物であるから、コメディ的な番組では、トランプは大変な人気者である。めちゃくちゃにコケにしながら、観客を歓喜させている。こういう番組がいくつもある。)


Stormy Daniels lawyer predicts Michael Cohen will ‘flip' on Trump
• Michael Avenatti also says Trump is in ‘panic mode’
• Daniels’ lawsuit against Donald Trump’s lawyer put on hold
Martin Pengelly
@MartinPengelly
Sun 29 Apr 2018 20.33 BSTFirst published on Sun 29 Apr 2018 20.11 BST

The lawyer representing the adult film actor Stormy Daniels said on Sunday Donald Trump was in “panic mode” and expected his attorney Michael Cohen to cooperate with investigations into the president.
“Mr Trump and the administration have concluded what I’ve been saying for weeks,” said Michael Avenatti, on CNN’s State of the Union. “That Michael Cohenis in a lot of trouble and he’s going to flip on the president.”
White House correspondents’ dinner: Michelle Wolf shocks media with Sarah Sanders attack

Read more
Cohen’s office, hotel room and home were raided by the FBI earlier this month, after a referral to the southern district of New York by special counsel Robert Mueller, who is investigating Russian election interference and alleged links between Trump aides and Moscow. Trump has denied collusion and called the investigation a “witch-hunt”.
FBI agents were looking among other things for documentation relating to Cohen’s orchestration shortly before the 2016 election of a payment to Daniels of $130,000, in return for her silence over a sexual relationship she claims to have had with Trump.
Daniels, whose real name is Stephanie Clifford, is suing to be released from the deal. She also alleges defamation by Cohen. Cohen indicated this week he will invoke his fifth amendment right to avoid self-incrimination. On Friday, the judge in California granted Cohen a 90-day delay, given that he is under criminal investigation in New York and that an indictment is “likely”.
The new edition of the National Enquirer tabloid, meanwhile, takes aim at Cohen under the headline: “Trump fixer’s secrets and lies!” The paper is owned by a Trump ally, David Pecker, and is often seen to do the billionaire’s bidding.
“This [National Enquirer cover] is the first effort on their part to undermine Mr Cohen’s credibility so they can claim when he does flip that he’s a liar,” Avenatti said, adding that it was “a pretty safe bet that Mr Trump … knew everything about this cover”.
Jack Shafer(@jackshafer)
Michael Cohen makes the National Enquirer pic.twitter.com/Bsg3Z1iUZS
April 28, 2018
Trump, who has denied a relationship with Daniels or knowledge of a payment to her, told Fox & Friends on Thursday Cohen was in fact representing him in the “crazy Stormy Daniels deal”.
Stormy Daniels' lawsuit against Donald Trump's lawyer put on hold

Read more
“He directly contradicted what he said on Air Force One,” Avenatti said, referring to a disavowal of knowledge of the payment earlier this month.
“He directly contradicted the nonsense that Michael Cohen has been trying to sell the American people for the last three months. And that is that Michael Cohen went out and did the agreement on his own and raised the $130,000 on his own and that Mr Trump never knew anything about it.”
Avenatti said Trump’s admission was “a critical mistake and this is what happens when you’re undisciplined in litigation. You may be able to be undisciplined in politics, you may be able to lie to the American press and the people, but you can’t lie in litigation. It comes back and bites you every time.”
He added: “It’s pretty transparent what’s going on here. Mr Trump realizes he’s in a lot of trouble and he’s in panic mode.”

2018年4月26日木曜日

On Ralph Hawtrey’s Thought and Things – Struggling to Build a Bridge between “Theory of Aspects” and “Science” Toshiaki Hirai (Sophia University)








On Ralph Hawtrey’s Thought and Things

 – Struggling to Build a Bridge between “Theory of Aspects” and “Science”

   

Toshiaki Hirai
(Sophia University)



1. Introduction
                              
Hawtrey (1879-1975) is well-known as an economist who developed a monetary theory of economic fluctuations in, e.g. Good and Bad Trade [Hawtrey, 1913] and Trade and Credit [Hawtrey, 1928] as well as advocating the so-called “Treasury View” - in contrast with Keynes’s understanding. Furthermore, he was severely critical of Keynes as the author of the Treatise from his own theoretical stance. 
Predominant in Hawtrey’s intellectual background was Cambridge – among other things, his experience as an Apostle was of great significance – although he was not to spend his academic life there. He worked as the only economist within the Treasury, which he entered after graduation and where he stayed until retirement.
  In the field of social philosophy he published two books – The Economic Problem1 [Hawtrey, 1926], and Economic Destiny [Hawtrey, 1944]. In addition, he left an unpublished book, Right Policy: The Place of Value Judgements in Politics, which was judged to have been written in the evening of his life (Hawtrey Papers, 12/2. Composed of 18 chapters, 528 sheets of typescript) 2. This critically examines the sphere of economics, sociology and political science, based on Moore’s ethics - including “the impossibility of the definition of goodness”. “Value Judgements” in the subtitle indicates judgements in view of (what he calls) “true ends”).
  What the present paper aims at, on the other hand, is Hawtrey’s philosophy which underlies his economic theory and social philosophy. Although he had taken an interest in philosophy throughout his life, he expressed his own philosophical view in only one unpublished book, Thought and Things (Hawtrey Papers, 12/1. Composed of 8 chapters, and 314 sheets of typescript). Although it is unclear at what stage of his development this was written, he dedicates a great deal of room to discussion of A Materialist Theory of Mind (Armstrong [1968]), showing it was written in his last years.
  Thought and Things has the following TOC: Ch.1 Aspects, Ch.2 Cause, Ch.3 Purpose, Ch.4 Thought, Ch.5 Truth and Inference, Ch.6 Science, Ch.7 Philosophy, Ch.8 Man and His World.
  The present paper runs as follows. Firstly, the theory of aspects which should be the substance of Hawtrey’s philosophy is examined. Secondly, we consider his basic
ideas on mind and matter. Finally, we evaluate his philosophy taking into account the context of philosophical currents in Cambridge at that time.
  No one seems to have studied Thought and Things3 so far, which may justify examination of it in a heuristic way. The vivid impression that I have received of the book as a whole is that it should be read in terms of an intellectual struggle searching for a bridge between a theory of aspect peculiar to Hawtrey and scientific knowledge. The main theme of this paper lies precisely here.


                        2. Theory of Aspect

2.1 Fundamental framework

To put Hawtrey’s philosophy in a nutshell, it may be seen as “a theory of aspect” 4. He put forward the main theme of Thought and Things in the Preface as follows.

    The leading theme of this book is the analysis of thought into the discernment of aspects in conscious experience. A predicate is an aspect of a subject. A relation is an aspect of two or more related terms.
     The mind, in discerning an aspect, makes contact with truth, but only
with truth about its own experience. (Preface, pp.1-2)

Taking this as the starting point, let us examine the fundamental framework of the theory of aspect argued in the book. (Incidentally, although “A predicate is … related terms.” is very difficult to understand, it is quoted here due to its importance. The meaning is made clearer on p.150, which we will deal with in Section 3.1 below.)

The main element is Mind. Before the mind, the field of consciousness which the mind can access expands. In other words, the mind creates the field of consciousness through making consciousness work.
What, then, does the main take as its object? In a word, “things”. However, the mind cannot get hold of things directly. It brings them into the field of consciousness, in fact, by means of the “senses” (sight, touch, hearing and so forth), that is, “sense experience”. This is called “conscious experience”, as a result of which “aspects” emerge.
The mind discerns some aspects from multiple aspects which appear in the field of consciousness. That is, “The discernment of an aspect is an activity of the mind exercised upon a state of the mind” (Preface, pp.1-2).
Although Hawtrey holds that an aspect potentially comes into being in the field of consciousness, he does not think that it objectively exists, independently of the mind. The mind discerns aspects which potentially exist, and aspects are not considered able to exist without the mind. In the above quotation, “The mind, in discerning an aspect, makes contact with truth, but only with truth about its own experience; as “but only …”, it should be noted in particular that truth is established only in relation to the mind’s experience.

      discernment of an aspect can only be true. That is so because the aspect is inherent in an experience which is wholly present to the mind. The mind notices an aspect which is already there to be selected for notice (my emphasis added, pp. 3-4).

An aspect is an aspect to the mind, and claims no independent existence. (p.123)

Let us recapitulate what have seen so far. The mind sees, a thing, say, a “chair”. Several aspects, through sense experience, “sight”, enter the field of consciousness of the mind, such as “it is made of wood; it has four legs; it is brown” and so forth. It depends on the state of mind how many of such aspects the mind can discern. This discernment is (the first form of) “thought”.
  Concerning the nature of aspect, another point is worth noting, namely that an aspect exists as a part of the whole in an inseparable way.

   An aspect has its own field, which is so much of the entire field as contributes
to it. But the aspect is not a part of its field. (p. 11)

… when we discern a part of any object, is not the part discerned an aspect of the whole? No, the aspect discerned is not the separable part but the relation of the part to the whole. (pp. 11-12)

What this means is that a part discerned should not be regarded as a portion separable from the whole, but as a part to the whole.

What calls for particular attention here is the existence of things; Hawtrey argues that the mind cannot possibly prove existence. What the mind receives is aspects only. However, as will be seen in Section 2, he is inclined to grasp aspects as intersubjective, or even implies that they are more objective, and more trans-time.

“The whole field of consciousness” is not confined to the field of consciousness mind can make contact with through “sense experience” – such as recognition of a person’s face, appreciation of paintings . Besides these, several states which are induced within the mind – from moral, feeling, volition, thought, concept through uncertainty, probability to mathematical propositions, mathematical inference, empirical inference – are also grasped in terms of aspects. The whole field of consciousness is considered to be composed of these two fields (cf.p.209. Fig.1)5.

Before proceeding to explain aspects obtained in these two fields, the first point to consider is why Hawtrey came to choose, as the title of this book, Thought and Things rather than A Theory of Aspect, for the title holds deep implications regarding his conception of philosophy.
  “Thought”, as we have seen, refers to the mind’s action in discerning aspects, epitomizing the theory of aspect which he attributed with a central role in Thought and Things. On the other hand, “Things” are what science sets as the object of research, epitomizing science. Thus he chose the title, Thought and Things, as implicating “A Theory of Aspect and Science”.
  These two words are proposed with the following implications. On the one hand,
they are presented as contrasting, although both are equally recognized. On the other hand, a way to organise or integrate them systematically6 is sought.

                       
(Fig.) The Whole Field of Consciousness

The whole field of consciousness      the field accessible through
sense experience
ex.recognition of a person’s face,
appreciation of paintings)
                      
the states induced within the mind
moral, feeling, volition, thought, concept
(uncertainty, probability)
(mathematical proposition, mathematical inference, empirical inference) and so forth
             

  In the theory of aspect, the existence of things is presupposed. The mind can neither prove their existence nor have means to recognize it correctly. Based on these recognitions the theory of aspect is developed. Meanwhile, in science the existence of things is also presupposed at the root of theory. Science cannot prove their existence. Despite these circumstances, the two fields of knowledge have been developed. Nevertheless, Hawtrey does not shirk the question: Should we allow this “dualism” to go on?

Starting from this fundamental recognition, Hawtrey proposes his theory of aspect as a philosophy of the field which science cannot grasp. We saw at the beginning of this paper that Hawtrey stated that “The leading theme of this book is the analysis of thought into the discernment of aspects in conscious experience”. This statement follows from the above recognition, which is summed up in the title, Thought and Things.

2.2 Aspect Obtained through Sense Experience

Let us take an example of an aspect obtained through sense experience.
Suppose that there is a chair in front of a person. The mind of the person grasps some aspects through sense experience such as seeing (sight) or touching (touch) it.
Here we must bear in mind the distinction between things and aspects. Hawtrey argues that one cannot prove the existence of things, which may show some affinity to Kant’s “thing in itself”. It is the aspects which appear in relation to a chair that the mind can discern through sense experience. Aspects stand in relation to a chair, and are to be discerned by the mind – they do not exist independently of the mind. Of the aspects which emerge before the mind, what the mind is able to discern become aspects. If not, they remain hidden, argues Hawtrey. For example, an artist can discern some aspects in painting that the majority of people fail to perceive.
  Although aspects may be “intersubjective” in the sense that they simultaneously appear in the two minds, this does not mean that they exist outside the two minds. Aspects could be defined as “intersubjective” existence in the field of consciousness.
  How could we be sure that anything besides one’s mind really exists? What exists outside one’s mind should be recognizable only when one’s mind discerns it at the level of aspects in the field of consciousness. Aspects thus discerned are accumulated in one’s mind, argues Hawtrey.
  Let us compare the theory of sense-data7 and the theory of aspect. What is similar is
that the former argues that the mind gets data from the object through sense experience, while the latter argues that the mind gets an aspect from the object through sense experience. What is different is that the former regards the data as subjective while the latter regards the aspect as intersubjective, appearing in the field of consciousness. It should be noted that the theory of aspect takes into consideration the states induced in the mind as well.
  Fussert’s “Noema” might correspond to what integrates various aspects. For Noema, which is not true reality, is obtained by grasping things consciously through sense experience (“things as objects of consciousness”). However, as Noema is considered to be subjective, it is different from aspects.

  So far we have stated that aspects, existing in the field of consciousness, are to be seen as intersubjective. However, the word, “intersubjective” here implies that aspects appear widely in the minds of many people. In this sense, this word comes closer to “objective”, as is borne out in Hawtrey’s argument on Platonic ideas.

… the foundation of the Platonic theory was the independent reality of the ideas. Their reality meant something different from the reality of things existing in time and space. … So l should be inclined to say that all aspects exist timelessly in the same way as the Platonic ideas.p.273

  Suppose that, say, there is a chair in front of ten people. There exist ten minds, each of which forms ten fields of consciousness through sense experience vis-à-vis the chair. In these circumstances there potentially exist several aspects which are commonly seen in these fields of consciousness. How many aspects are discerned will depend on the state of each mind. Thus interpreted, aspects are intersubjective, and with an increasing number of minds the aspects may approach an “objective” condition.

2.3 Aspects Obtained as the States Induced in the Mind

The field of consciousness is not only open to sense experience but also extends through the states induced within the mind (cf. Fig. 1 and p.209), which may include, for example: moral, feeling, volition, thought, concept; uncertainty, probability; mathematical propositions, mathematical inferences, empirical inferences.
  They are different, in nature, from the aspects obtained through sense experience, for they are aspects which are induced in the mind, to a certain extent independent of the outer world. Let us take thought, concepts, knowledge, which Hawtrey mentioned as representative. (The others are kept for other occasions).


(a) Thought                   

“Thought” is discernment of an aspect. Hawtrey states that “I would go further and say that all thought consists in the discernment of aspects of experience. … Each possible thought consists in noticing a particular aspect, that is to say, selecting this aspect for attention from the whole field of consciousness” (p.109).
 Thought centers around a proposition. It establishes itself, choosing aspects and combining them. The aspects thus chosen and discerned are either “attributes” or “relations” (cf. p.150). That is, by combining aspects as “attributes” and those as “relations”, a thought establishes itself. While sense experience is simultaneous, thought is characterised by inference.
  Thought may belong to the stage next to intuitive aspects, which have no interpretation – that is, the stage when an interpretation of experience is made.
This is clear in the following.
   
   The aspect discerned is an attribute or a relation. In the case of an intuitive aspect, untouched by interpretation, the predicate has no other subject than the field of consciousness or a part of the field. The interpretation of experience supplies the predicates with subjects and the relations with terms: things, persons and places, in which the aspects are to be discerned. (p.150)

This passage has much the same meaning as the following part of the first quotation in this paper – “A predicate is an aspect of a subject. A relation is an aspect of two or more related terms”. That is, “an aspect of a subject” is “an intuitive aspect” while “a relation … terms” corresponds to “the interpretation of experience”.

(b) Concept              

With regard to what occurs within the mind in relation to a concept, two terms are proposed – familiarity and association.
 Familiarity is a feeling attached to a concept (cf. p.143). It has two types (cf. p.135). One is the familiarity with the particular past occurrences of an aspect, to which associations point. This occurs in the initial stage of the formation of a concept. The other is the familiarity with the concept itself, which develops thereafter. The associations usually stop there.
  The mind embraces several aspects accordingly as, through a certain “familiarity”, associations continue to be induced. By combining these aspects a certain “concept” comes into being (cf. p. 144)8.
  A concept is an abstraction, and an aspect is elaborated by interpretation. If a certain aspect is familiarized, it becomes a starting point for associations. By following it, the mind can search for its past experience through “memory”.

(c) Knowledge            
“Knowledge” is a belief grounded on several aspects discerned (cf. pp.151, 199). Knowledge accumulated in the mind is composed of “familiarized” aspects and “familiarized” concepts (cf. p.154).
We may put it thus. A combination of aspects, through which a concept is formed, becomes familiar through repetitive occurrence of a particular type (cf. p.145). A façade of aspects through which a concept is recognized becomes a key to a series of “associations” (cf. p.163).

Upon the stock of memories and concepts is built the structure of thoughts or beliefs constituting knowledge. (p.150)

The concept is the subjects of which the aspects are predicates and relations.
  (p.141).

 What we have so far seen is summarized in Fig.2.

Fig.2Thought, Concept, Knowledge
Thought Discernment of an aspect. Inferential. The stage at which an interpretation of experience is made.

Concept Several aspects combined through association of familiarity by the mind.
          
Knowledge  Belief grounded on several aspects discerned.

“Knowledge” accumulated within the mind = “familiar” aspects + “familiar” concepts

   
3. Mind and Matter

3.1 The Main Theme              

As already pointed out, the title of Hawtrey’s book, “Thought and Things”, which the present paper intends to examine, has the implication of “A Theory of an Aspect and Science”, which could be also expressed as “Mind and Matter”.
  Hawtrey takes both mental occurrences, such as thought, imagination, feeling, volition and material objects, as “facts”. This is characteristic of his broad approach. He argues that although a “thing in itself” should be unrecognizable, the mind can discern aspects through sense experience, while he accepts scientific knowledge by recognizing the existence of “material objects” – he seems to make a philosophical effort to incorporate scientific knowledge into the theory of aspect.
  Mental occurrences are, as we have seen, the principal actors of Hawtrey’s theory of aspect, and he argues that they are “facts”.

What is presented to the mind is either sense experience or the operation of the mind itself, thought, imagination, feeling or volition. These mental occurrences are facts. (p.209)

At the same time, he argues that material objects are “facts” as well. In his argument here, a “causal hypothesis” appears in relation to sense experience, in which material substance is included as fact. Arguing along this line, he seems to be considering how “a theory of aspect” should be connected with “science”.
  If one were to focus solely on the mind and confine attention to a “theory of aspect” in which sense experience and the states induced within the mind appear, one could not explain the world which science has so far explored. Moreover, the states induced within the mind, as we have seen, include not only thought and concepts but also mathematical propositions, mathematical inferences and empirical inference, all of which are used as indispensable tools in science. If this is the case we must recognise the fundamental importance of a philosophy which is not driven away by science, exploring how the “theory of aspect” could be compatible with “science”. For Hawtrey, inquiry in this direction appears to be the essential challenge.
  “It does not address the true solution to argue mind and matter separately. But philosophy which stresses material only and neglects mind misses the fundamental problem.” – According to Hawtrey, as science has developed, philosophy, which neglects or ignores the philosophical point of view which focuses on mind, has become more and more influential. Logical positivism and behaviorism are emblematic of this trend. In his philosophy Hawtrey shows a keenly critical attitude towards these tendencies. Let us consider a passage, though a little long, which makes this point clear.
                                                                                             
Sense experience puts in a claim to be something more than mental, in that it seems to be imposed on the mind by some agency other than the mind. And the causal hypothesis supports the claim by tracing sense experience through chains of causation to matter.
       The causal hypothesis, in the form which we instinctively believe, includes the reality of matter. We take the outside agency of causation to be a fact, and each particular material object to be a fact. And, as I have shown, other human beings are given the status of facts, independently of the reality of matter. Their thoughts and feelings are held to be facts like one’s own.  When I think about an actual material object, my thought is one fact and the material object is another.
       A material object embodies the concept of its kind, and exhibits the aspects contained in the concept, together with the Aristotelian accidents, aspects which belong to it as an empirical particular and are not deducible from the concept.
       Thoughts and feelings form part of the field of consciousness and exhibit aspects and concepts, though they do not fit into kinds so simply as material objects.  (p.209)

A characteristic common to all the mental occurrences of which experience consists is that they are real. Reality is an aspect discerned in them, and the causal hypothesis extends to matter the same concept of reality that is discerned in experience. That is an inevitable inference from the hypothesis which traces sense experience to causes emanating from a world of material objects. (p.211)

Insofar as the human being is an entity that recognizes everything through the action of the mind, science by scientists cannot be explored without this procedure.  The above passage, “A material object embodies the concept of its kind, and exhibits the aspects contained in the concept, together with … from the concept” is grounded precisely on this recognition. “A material object” is related to a “concept” and an “aspect”.
  The following passage also shows his stance in moving on beyond “dualism” (separation between mind and matter), by pointing out the relation between the “theory of aspect” and “science”.

The discernment of an aspect is an activity of the mind exercised upon a state of the mind, but the common aspect of the field of consciousness and the nature posited by science is the essential link between mind and fact. (Preface, pp.1-2)

An aspect which exists in the field of consciousness according to the theory of aspect, and is nature as posited by science should constitute an essential link between mind and fact.

Hawtrey does not take the view that ascribes substance to matter alone (i.e. Materialism). He argues that the causal hypothesis, which “takes over the concepts of reality and of extension over time, and applies them to matter, … does not absolutely require the reality to have all the characteristics attributed to matter”. (p.253b)

However, Hawtrey reveals that his own theory of aspects has some problems as well.

But the dualism which makes reality consist of matter and mind, and allows importance only to mind, is far from satisfying the requirements of logos.
    I have suggested at the end of Chapter VI that Professor Armstrong’s form of materialism might supersede this dualism. Matter would be the only form of existence, while mind would be a real activity of matter. Any genuine simplification in philosophy may be presumed to be in harmony with logos.  At the same time I do not think a simplification of the concept of substance goes far towards rationalising the causal hypothesis. The concept of matter as the substance in which causal efficacy is rooted, is a mere token of reality.  An anthropocentric philosophy does not fit into a material universe, in which man occupies a physically insignificant place. (p.310)

3.2 Science

As we have seen, Hawtrey sets out his “theory of aspect” as the main pillar of his philosophy. At the same time, however, he recognizes the role which “science” has played, and tries to see how it could be compatible with the “theory of aspect”. However, in Thought and Things he does not arrive at a final solution. Together with “Thought and Things”, we find expressions such as “A Theory of Aspect and Science”, “Mind and Material”, “Mind and Facts”. All of them are expressions showing how this dualism could be avoided.
  That said, let us see how he takes the problem which science or philosophy of science finds itself faced with.
 Hawtrey does not see the theory of aspect and science as being built on different principles. He tries to view science, rather, as an extension of the theory of aspect (which could be generalised as philosophy in this context).
Let us remember that science embraces physics, which ranges from macro phenomena like celestial movement and the structure of the universe to micro phenomena such as the origin of material – molecules, atoms, atomic nuclei, DNA – or physiology, which explores human organs such as the brain and heart in relation to the movement of nerve cells. The development of science has exerted great influence on the worldview of mankind from the 17th century to this day, excluding philosophy and theology from these problems. Under these circumstances, how did Hawtrey, who proposed a theory of aspect, attempt to position science within his philosophy? – This is the problem we address here.

Philosophers have sought an aspect of the universe which will be plausible, which, that is, will be exposed to the least possible degree of intrinsic doubtfulness, and will command the highest attainable degree of credibility.  At the outset they are faced with the difficulty that what is known about the Universe is very incomplete. In order to form an aspect of the whole, they must fill up the gaps so far as they can. That is to say, they must construct a concept of the entire realm of existence. In doing so, they are pursuing the method of scientific discovery by framing hypotheses to account for experience, but they are trespassing beyond the limits of science, because they are adopting hypotheses which cannot be verified. In default of verification they have to appeal to intrinsic probability. (pp.257-258)

In these conditions philosophers considered the universe. Although a method of scientific discovery was applied, scientists in the modern sense were yet to appear.
 
  Here the “causal hypothesis” comes into play. 

The causal hypothesis introduces into thought its own characteristic form of inference. Cause implies effect. Empirical reasoning seeks a concept with   causal properties, to explain some sequence in experience. The causal properties may be nothing more than a crude rule to the effect that a certain type of event is always followed by a certain other type of event. (p.169)

Causal hypotheses are used both in the theory of aspect and the theory of science, having, respectively, mind and matter as initial cause.

  Mind and matter have been posited by the causal hypothesis, each to be the vehicle of its own characteristic causal activity: matter can serve as the vehicle of physical movement, because it has spatial characteristics; mind can be the vehicle of conscious experience. Each acts in its own special sphere. (p.253)

Matter is the hypothetical vehicle of causality, and must in some way carry the spatial and temporal relations which are the subject matter of physical causality. (p.263)

Here we need to turn our attention to the theory of science. When a causal hypothesis is adopted in science, it cannot determine the initial cause however far it might trace it back. For the initial mover cannot, by nature, explained be by a causal hypothesis. It is “matter” that is introduced as the driving force of a causal relation. Scientific explanation depends on it.
  However, Hawtrey argues that the concept of “matter” used in science is far from complete. In the first place, even if a “causal feature” and a “spatial feature” are made use of, the relation to integrate the two is by no means clarified.

  But when we ask what is in the concept of matter which determines all the causal properties, there is no answer. Hume’s scepticism holds the field. The concept of matter is incomplete, for the causal properties are super-imposed on the spatial qualities without any specifiable relation calculated to unify them. (p.260)

Scientists are satisfied nowadays with the acceptance of their conclusions as a mere description of the orderliness of experience. The reality of matter is not an alternative to this position, but is an additional hypothesis, the plausibility of which depends on the degree of credibility of the concept of matter itself. (p.259)

When we carry the assumptions of science into the sphere of life and of mind, the incompleteness of the concept of matter becomes more conspicuous. The discovery of formulas governing the behaviour of the sub-atoms in living organisms is no more than an aspiration. If it is ever to be fulfilled, we cannot foresee even in barest outline what the concept will be like. (p.260)

Hawtrey’s view in these spheres includes another important concept – “probability”. This embraces not only calculable but also incalculable probability. Hawtrey argues, moreover, that this is applicable not only to mental processes but also to the sphere of the substance of matter.

   Only exceptionally is the probability of a particular empirical proposition susceptible of numerical measurement. In other cases there is a direct judgement of a greater or smaller degree of probability. There seems to be no reason why the same mental process which leads to an estimate of probability in those cases should not apply to the plausibility of a view of the universe, such as the reality of matter. (p.259)

These observations show strong affinity with Keynes’s concept of “probability”.

3.3 Criticism of Behaviorism and Logical Positivism

Hawtrey pursued the investigation into how scientific recognition could be bridged with the “theory of aspect”. On the other hand, he made explicit criticism of the philosophy which stresses the importance of science, emphasizing matter. He argued against behaviorism, logical positivism, scientism, materialism (and historical materialism). Here we will consider the first two objects of his criticism.

(a) Behaviorism

Of the stance taken in behaviorism on the delicate relation between science and mind, Hawtrey is critical. Behaviorism argues that the mental activity of human beings is closely related to the nerves or some portion of brain, so that irrespective of, or independent of, how one thinks, the mental activity of human beings should be explicable.

   Not only does sense experience correspond to the state of the physical senses,    
but it is held that the mental processes of thought, feeling and volition, which intervene in the making of decisions, also have physical counterparts in the brain and nervous system, forming a self-contained causal chain, the action of which is independent of the mind. The mind would be no more than a passive record of the physical sequence, an epiphenomenon. (p.226)
                                                                                              
The postulate of behaviourism is a hypothesis which would extend the mechanistic explanation to the facts of psychology and to our apparently purposive action. .… The postulate therefore remains for its adherents an act of faith.  (p.227)

How should we understand the relation between the mind’s conscious action and the functional activity of the person’s brain and nerve system corresponding to it? Behaviorists as well as materialists stress the above postulate (materialistic view), while Hawtrey supports the “mind” view. As have seen, Hawtrey, moreover, aims to explore the relation between mind and matter - thought and things.

The postulate of behaviourism denies the common sense belief that the purposive behaviour of human bodies can only be interpreted as presupposing conscious direction. …There is a fundamental difference between a field of consciousness and a field of mechanistic causation.  (p.241)

The question is whether there can be a perfect correspondence between the field of consciousness, in which action is determined by preference, and the field of mechanism, in which action is determined by causal uniformity. (p.242)

Let us take up a simple case. Suppose someone is faced with a choice between two flowers – rose and amaryllis. The person chooses amaryllis, for he knows that the host in the family who invited him is very fond of amaryllis, though he himself loves roses. How could a behaviorist explain this phenomenon in terms of the activity of a brain and nervous system? This must be impossible to explain even if science makes miraculous progress. The above case of the rose and amaryllis is a problem which an analysis based on the activity of brain cells and the nervous system cannot tackle.

I believe the theory of aspects has a bearing on this question [whether or not physiology will come to be able to explain behavior in a self-contained way independently of the mental processes], in that the discernment of aspects is an essentially mental process, which cannot have an adequate physical counterpart. (p. 227. The square brackets are mine.)

Conscious direction by human beings has the maximum degree of intrinsic probability.p.263

By contrast, Hawtrey makes to some extent a positive assessment of Gestalt psychology, stating that it shares some elements in common with the theory of aspect.

Thus the Gestalt Psychologists may be regarded as introducing aspects into
psychology. (p.245)

Hawtrey, however, comments that, alas, the Gestalt psychologists express support of the behaviorists’ view of the relation between mind and matter.


(b) Logical Positivism

Hawtrey is also critical of logical positivism, which excludes metaphysics from its field of study on the ground that it is not verifiable, arguing that it lacks the point of view of perception in the field of consciousness.
  Logical positivism regards verification as essential to the meaning of a proposition. Hawtrey takes A.J. Ayer, a representative of this school, as object of his criticism.

His [Ayer’s] twofold division of knowledge into empirical judgements, which are subject to verification, and analytic judgements, which are tautologous, supports the extreme empiricism of logical positivism. (p.181)

     Professor Ayer in his contribution to The Revolution in Philosophy (p.74) explains that “statements like those of metaphysics, to the truth of which no empirical observation could possibly be relevant, are ruled out as factually meaningless. The emphasis here is on the word ‘factually’ – not capable of stating facts”. (p.182)

However, he argues that aspects which exist in the state of consciousness, which is the theater of the theory of aspect, are indeed essential to our recognition, and yet not of a nature which requires verification.
                                                                                                                  
  But it is not only aspects of sense experience that provide a kind of knowing which does not need verification. Aspects of states of consciousness other than sense experience are of the same kind. (p.182a)

The contention of logical positivism that verifiability is essential to truth is untenable. (p.182b)

Hawtrey is highly critical of Ayer’s explanation of Kant’s analytical judgment and synthetic judgment from the point of view of the theory of aspect. Above all, the following observation regarding mathematics is worth noting. As shown in Fig.1, “The Whole Field of Consciousness”, mathematical propositions and mathematical inference are included in “the states induced within mind”.

   Professor Ayer criticised Kant’s argument for the synthetic nature of mathematics on the ground that the question was not a psychological one but a logical one. But knowledge is psychological. To treat the matter as purely logical meant ignoring the limitations to which the human mind’s knowledge is subject. (p.179)

Hawtrey argues that mathematics is not purely logical, but is subject to the limitations of the mind’s knowledge.

Recognition of a kind of knowing of physical objects which claims the same kind of directness as the propositions of mathematics, conflicts with this division [empirical judgment and analytical judgment]. (pp. 181-182)

In fact, logical positivism as composed of empirical judgment which requires verification and analytical judgment which is tautology (mathematics belongs to this category) embodies self-contradiction as philosophy of science, for the reason why mathematics is required together with empirical judgment is not clarified at all.
  Moreover, Hawtrey argues the difference between “empirical reasoning” (it should be noted that this is reasoning in the theory of aspect, different from empirical judgment in logical positivism) and mathematical reasoning.

     While in empirical reasoning synthesis means a comparison of objects with a view to revealing common qualities or aspects, in mathematical reasoning comparison is dispensed with, because numbers are known a priori to have the common characteristic of all being linked to their neighbouring numbers by the plus-one relation. (p.144)

It is in his argument of probability that Hawtrey’s point of argument becomes clearer.

Probability, like size or distance, is an aspect to be discerned; it is an aspect of the thought which asserts a proposition. (p.158)

“An aspect of the thought … proposition” might basically rest on the same idea as the concept of probability in Keynes’s Treatise on Probability and Russell’s subsequent considerations.

  Thus a judgement of probability applied to a philosophical interpretation of the universe comes under the head of Lord Russell’s “intrinsic doubtfulness”, or “degree of credibility”. (p.257)

To recapitulate, Hawtrey thinks that “mathematical proposition, mathematical reasoning, probability” belong to “the states induced within mind”, and is critical of logical positivism, which neglects the mind and argues that science can make progress by excluding ideas related to the mind as “metaphysical”. First, it is a misconception of mathematics and probability. Secondly, it is a misconception of science (though science per se remains important).


4. Philosophical Currents in Cambridge

Hawtrey was an ardent supporter of G.E. Moore’s philosophy, and its influence continued throughout his life. Moreover, he was an apostle, and deeply involved in in the Cambridge current of philosophy. In Thought and Things, naturally enough, he referred to Cambridge philosophers such as Moore, Russell, Keynes, Wittgenstein, Ramsey and so forth in various pages9 (although on the whole there are few if any points in which he shows a critical attitude towards them – despite the differences between his view and theirs).
  To my knowledge, there is no material in the book indicating what sort of discussion was held among them. That said, in this section, let us make a brief survey of the currents of Cambridge philosophy, taking Hawtrey’s philosophy into consideration.

4.1 G.E. Moore

It is well-known that Moore came to lead Cambridge philosophy in a new direction, criticizing MacTaggart, who represented Hegelian Idealism in the UK. Influenced by Moore, Russell stated that he, too, had decided to depart from that line.
  That said, Moore was not an empiricist, and was very critical of pragmatism, as can be seen in his criticism of James’ rationalism. 
With regard to the controversy between scientism and the Neo-Kantian School which advocated “Return to Kant” as a motto and could be characterised as transcendental, Moore was sympathetic with the latter.
  Moore’s s way of thinking has a certain affinity with that of Socrates and Plato. The approach, asking “what is Goodness” and pursuing it, is strongly reminiscent of Socrates. And yet, he does not move forward to a theory of ideas. Rather, he conceives of “Goodness” in a presentative way, arguing that it is impossible to define. Moreover, he criticizes, a number of philosophical approaches, including utilitarianism, from the point of view of intuitionism, stating that they are subject to the “naturalistic fallacy”. The idea of “sense data”, which influenced Russell among others, is also important for a knowledge of Moore’s philosophy.
  The ideas Moore proposed exerted a great influence on Keynes and his contemporaries including Hawtrey, Lytton Strachey, Shove and Leonard Woolf. They are, on the whole, critical of utilitarianism (Here Keynes’s view on Edgeworth (1926) is worth noting).

  As is clear from his way of argument, Moore was inclined to take language very seriously. Thus he came to address the problem of language, and pay increasing attention to “ordinary language” and “common sense” in his philosophy.
  Attention to “ordinary language” was the stance adopted by the latter-day Wittgenstein - although he endorsed this element even in the Tractus Logico-Philosophicus. Moore regularly attended the lectures (1930-33) by Wittgenstein, who had returned to Cambridge, to the extent that he eventually published his notes on them.
It should be added that Hawtrey and Keynes seem not to have shared an interest
in “ordinary language”.

4.2 Russell

Russell’s philosophy is known as “logical atomism”, and is characterized thus:
 
  The reason that I call my doctrine logical atomism is because the atoms    that I wish to arrive at as the sort of last residue in analysis are logical atoms and not physical atoms. Some of them will be what I call ‘particulars’ – such things as little patches of colour or sounds, momentary things – and some of them will be predicates or relations and so on. The point is that the atom I wish to arrive at is the atom of logical analysis, not the atom of physical analysis. (Russell, 1985 [1918], p.37)

Russell and Whitehead tried to reduce mathematics to logic in the Principia
Mathematica. Logical atomism makes a similar endeavor in the field of philosophy.
Russell’s philosophy, like Wittgenstein’s, became the bible of the “Vienna Circle” which advocated Logical Positivism (this was against the Neo-Kantian School, and adopted a motto, “purge metaphysics from science”).
  Logical atomism was to exert a deep influence on Keynes’s Treatise on
Probability. However, on the whole, more scholars seem to have taken a critical
attitude towards it in Cambridge. Wittgenstein showed some discordance from the
outset, and finally came to a clean break. Keynes also seems to have become
critical of logical atomism later. Ramsey was also critical. He moved in the
direction of Pragmatism. Hawtrey’s philosophy, Things and Thought, took a huge
distance from logical atomism, although no critical comments are to be found
there.
  There is a clear difference between Moore’s philosophy and Russell’s. The
contrasting relation can be summed up as ordinary language vs. ideal
language; or intuitionism vs. formal logic/logical atomism.

4.3 Keynes

Greatly influenced by Moore and Russell, Keynes wrote a dissertation for his King’s College fellowship - the prototype of what was to be published later as A Treatise on Probability. The book makes two major departures. 10
  The first departure consists in an inquiry into epistemology and logic in a world in which “probability” defined as “a degree of rational belief between propositions” was predominant. He stressed the “objective” logical relation between a premise and a proposition. By applying this relation to the field of “probability”, Keynes aimed at building the philosophical foundations for logical judgment based on human reason. “Indirect knowledge”, dealt with in A Treatise on Probability, is obtained through argument. When an argument is composed of a complicated set of sub-arguments, a knowledge of formal logic is indispensable. Thus recognition by rational human beings in the form of an axiomatic theoretical system is required. This is the main aim addressed in Book II.
Another departure is his justification of “Induction”. The theory of probability developed in Books I and II is directly connected to Book III, “Induction and Analogy”, in which Keynes argues that “induction is a problem of formal logic (the existence of the relation of probability) rather than a problem of facts”.
  According to him, induction is composed of “analogy” and “pure induction” (the latter refers to simple repetition of cases). Of the two, it is analogy which matters. He argues that a priori probability is obtained by analogy.
When knowledge is imperfect, analogy proceeds to the higher stages with the aid of pure induction. He went on to argue that induction can be justified, insofar as the number of “features of a thing” (such as “it has four legs”, “it has hair”) is limited either by “the method of perfect analogy” (which is due to an individual introspection) or by “other inductive method” (the method, by finding negative analogy with the aid of pure induction, of approaching perfect analogy).

Keynes did not write any article or book on philosophy thereafter, so we cannot know exactly whether he continued his early philosophy or not, except for a few short essays. That said, I am inclined to take the view that he changed his philosophy later for the following reasons.
Among other things, what mattered was the relation with Ramsey. It is well known that Ramsey favored pragmatism11, unlike Moore and Keynes, and put forward a theory of subjective probability, which differed from Keynes’s theory of objective probability.
Meanwhile, Ramsey leveled some harsh criticism at Keynes’s Treatise on Probability, a great deal of which Keynes (1931) accepted.
  Keynes expressed his view that formal the logic of Russell and (the early-day) Wittgenstein proceeded in such a way as to be void of content, becoming “dry bones”, and ultimately excluding not only all experience but also almost all principles of rational thinking.
  Ramsey, by contrast, proposed a kind of pragmatism which addresses human logic, criticizing Wittgenstein (it is well known that serious discussion with Ramsey, and indeed with Sraffa,12 made a great contribution to the emergence of the latter-day Wittgenstein).
  Ramsey distinguished human logic from formal logic. Man has a useful mental habit of dealing with things provided by sense and memory, and so has a consistent system by applying this to a logic of probability. Although calculation of probability belongs to formal logic, a degree of our belief should be like a part of clothes, and should be close to our sense or memory rather than to formal logic. Thus Keynes largely came round to accepting Ramsey’s view.
This is not to say, however, that Keynes was converted to Ramsey’s philosophy, for the latter-day Keynes did not accept series of subjective probability or pragmatism. What Keynes emphasized in “My Early Beliefs” (Keynes, 1939) is that he himself gradually departed from rationalism, and came to emphasize the importance of the ambiguity of the real world, and with it, therefore, custom and so forth13.

  As we have seen, Hawtrey expressed a sympathetic view of probability as expressed in Keynes’s Treatise on Probability14. He saw it, in terms of aspects, as one of the states induced within the mind.

Since no belief can be absolutely certain, every thought embodying a belief may be said to present this aspect (probability), but in general the aspect remains a mere potentiality and is not noticed. Only when the process by which a judgement has been arrived at is felt to be in some way insufficiently cogent to form a basis for action, is attention turned to its doubtfulness and it enters the stock of knowledge labelled “probable”. (p.161)

It should be added that there is no evidence left as to how Keynes judged Hawtrey’s theory of aspect. 


4.4 Wittgenstein

Around 1930, Wittgenstein began to doubt the “theory of logical determination” (Takiura, 1983, p.159) which is the principal framework of Tractus Logico-Philosophicus (written in 1918, and published in 1922), and through trial and error thereafter wrote the substance of Part 1 of Philosophical Investigations at the end of 1936 (the final version in 1949. This seems to be the beginning of the latter-day Wittgenstein who put forward the “language game” theory.
  Tractus Logico-Philosophicus is said to have made a great contribution to the emergence of logical positivism together with The Philosophy of Logical Atomism (Russell, 1918). Especially in the development of the latter, Russell stated that he was greatly influenced by Wittgenstein, the author of the former, so it was understood that the two scholars were working in the same direction.
Even in this period, in fact, there was a great difference between the two. Wittegenstein was very critical of Russell’s philosophy. Moreover, as we saw above, Russell continued to stick to, and develop “a theory of logical atomism”, shifting from “an empirical approach” to “a rationalist approach”. See Pears). In the same period, Wittgenstein was to be deeply engaged in “language game” theory, so relations between the two went from tension to final rupture.

4.5 Theory of Aspect in Hawtrey and Wittgenstein

Let us now consider the difference between the two in theory of aspect. In the case of Hawtrey, “aspect” is intersubjective (semi-objective). There exist aspects (in this sense they are close to Platonic idea). He argues that each mind can grasp them. He tries to grasp things in such a way as many kinds of aspects are attached to them. Important concepts are then developed from them.
   What needs to be emphasized here is that Hawtrey’s theory of aspects can be traced back to Hawtrey (1912). It was read at the ‘Friday Club’ meeting of artists.
Though he argued out his theory of aspect, confining it to art – painting, music and so forth – we can see sufficient continuity to Thought and Things. One passage in particular is worth quoting.

If you have grasped what I mean by an aspect you will see of what vital importance it is to our minds. Both memory and imagination, so far as they relate to the objects of sense, deal primarily in aspects. Detail is filled in mainly by reason. (p.3)

On the other hand, in the case of Wittgenstein15, aspect, which is discussed in Part 2, Chapter 11 in Philosophical Investigations [Part 2 was completed in 1949], is regarded as a kind of image grasped by the mind. And it is perceived as a different image by each mind (see Jastrow’s famous “Duck-Rabbit Picture”). It is very subjective, so it does not exist objectively 16.
 Let us now go on to consider some of the similarities seen in the two
philosophies. Firstly, both show some closeness to Köhler’s Gestalt psychology
(cf.TT, 234, 244), and share psychological cogitations in common. Secondly, both
are critical of scientism and logical positivism. Thirdly, both are critical of
Russell’s logical atomism.
  Speaking of points of difference, the “language game ideas” adopted by
Wittgenstein are not recognizable in Hawtrey. In general, Wittgenstein attaches
weight to language, ordinary language, while Hawtery does not.


4.6 Hawtrey’s Philosophy Re-stated

Hawtrey took the perception of the field of consciousness through sense experience as the foundation of philosophy. In that sense his philosophy differs from the Platonic theory of ideas. We cannot prove the existence of things. We can grasp aspects consciously through sense experience, and have a capacity of recognition only through building them within the mind.
  On the other hand, Hawtrey criticizes logical positivism, which argues that because metaphysics cannot be empirical, science should expel it from the object of research.  He argues that it is a lacking in the view of perception of the field of consciousness.
  Finally, I would point out the two passages useful in understanding Hawtrey’s philosophical stance.

The reality of sense experience is the indispensable premise of any form of empiricism. (p.182)

Value judgements are among those metaphysical statements “to the truth of which no empirical observation could possibly be relevant”. (p.182b)

We have outlined the philosophical currents in Cambridge, which suffice to evidence its importance as a center in the world. It was under these circumstances that Hawtrey made his own philosophical explorations. Let me repeat, unhappily, we cannot find any document showing what kind of philosophical controversy Hawtrey engaged in with these philosophers under these circumstances.


5. Conclusion

We have examined Hawtrey’s unpublished book, Thought and Things. The main theory there seems to be the theory of aspect. It focuses on the mind’s selection which appears in the field of consciousness, from which it tries to explain the various mental products such as concept, knowledge and so forth. Hawtrey conceives of “an aspect” as intersubjective, or even extending to a more objective level.
  Then, as the title, “Thought and Things” shows, Hawtrey tackles the thorny old problem of how the relation between “mind and matter” or “theory of aspect and science” should be understood. We might say that the final aim of this unpublished book was to explore how one can build a bridge between the two, without falling into dualism. Though he did not reach the final answer, he developed his argument compellingly, aiming at building a bridge.
  Hawtrey was severely critical of behaviorism and logical positivism, which  looked at the world from a scientific point of view neglecting the mind. These criticisms are worth attention, for they argue that behaviorism and logical positivism are based on a misunderstanding of science and mathematics. Hawtrey points out the following – Concerning science, a causal hypothesis introduces “matter” as its prime mover without arguing a relation between “a causal property” and “spatial property”, so that the concept of matter is incomplete. Moreover, when it comes to the field of life and mind, the incompleteness of the concept of matter is much more conspicuous.
As for mathematical considerations, when we remember that Hawtrey argues “mathematical proposition” and “probability” in terms of “theory of aspect”, the distance from the approach of logical positivism is strikingly evident (See Fig. 1).



 1) Hirai (2007) examines this.
 2) Hirai (2009) and Hirai (2012) examine this.
3) In Google Scholar and EBSCO the author was able to find neither papers discussing Hawtrey’s philosophy nor documents concerning Thought and Things.
4) In the philosophical world, “the theory of aspect” is used for the argument in Part II of Philosophical Investigations by Wittgenstein (see, e.g. Shoroeder [2010], Arahata [2013]). There is no place for Hawtrey. For the relation between the two, see Section 4.
5) The theory of aspect examined so far is similar to Husserl’s phenomenology as a study of “conscious experience as experienced from a point of subjective view” (“intentionality, that is, directness of experience towards things in the world”. In that this experience includes “sense, thought, memory, imagination, feeling, volition, will”, there is a similarity.
However, in Thought and Things, there is no reference to phenomenology. That said, this idea emerges in phenomenology, deeply influenced by Kant. And evidently, Hawtrey himself was directly influenced by Kant. His answer to Hume was that the orderliness of sense experience dwells not in things in themselves but in the constitution of the observing mind. “Form is not to be looked for in the object in itself, but in the subject [the field of consciousness] to which the object appears”. (p.288. [   ] is the author’s)
6) Armstrong (1968) is mentioned. See T&T, pp.253b-253c, p.310.
7) See the theory of sense-data developed in Russell (1912). There it is argued as a relation between “appearance” and “reality”.
  8) “Familiarity” by Hawtrey is analogous to “Acquaintance” by Russell.
9) For frequent references, the following are mentioned: Russell (pp.13, 18,20,28,43, 132a, 132b, 139,140,159,160,161,165,166, 166a, 184, 185, 186,189, 195, 197, 198, 204, 209,257, 285, 286), Moore (pp.6-7, 96,100-102,130,131,132,132a,132b,182b), Keynes (156,157, 158,159, 160, 161).
 10) See Hirai (2002). 
11) There is no reference to pragmatism in Thought and Things.
  12) See Kurz (2009).
13) Itoh1999, p.58argues thus: Accepting Ramsey’s criticism, Keynes came to
relinquish “a logicism interpretation of probability” in A Treatise on
Probability and sought the “connection between uncertainty and rationality”
in “the world of transcendent propositions”, which is evident in The General
Theory.
  14) In “Probability” (pp.155a-161) in Thought and Things, three main themes
in Keynes’s Treatise on Probability – probability in the field of
immeasurability, the definition of probability, and “induction and analogy” –
are examined. Among other things, the second and the third points are
examined, taking Russell’s argument in Human Knowledge (esp. “intrinsic
doubtfulness”) into consideration.
15) There are two kinds of aspects in Wittgenstein – “aspect of changes” and
“continuous aspects”. Though there is a divergence of view as to which Wittgenstein attached more weight to, the latter appears to be closer to Hawtrey’s aspects.
 16) On aspects, there are references to Philosophical Investigations  (Wittgenstein, 1963) in Thought and Things (pp.11, 12,109, 110,131). However, Hawtrey has nothing to say about the difference between the two. Incidentally, reference to “theory of language game” is found on p. 194, while reference to the Tractus Logico-Philosophicus (Wittgenstein, 1922) is found on pp.163, 164, 165.




References

1. The references which appear in Thought and Things (the places where necessary information such as publishers, the year of publication, etc, is missing) are retained as they originally appeared.

Adrian, E.D. 1947. The Physical Background of Perception. Oxford University Press.
Aristotle  Metaphysics, translated by Sir. D. Ross.
Armstrong, D.M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of Mind. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Ayer, A. J. 1936. Language, Truth and Logic (2nd ed.). Gollancz.
Ayer, A. J. 1940. The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge. Macmillan.
Berkeley 1710. The Principles of Human Knowledge.
Broad, C.D. 1925. The Mind and Its Place in Nature. Kegan Paul.
Cornford, F.M.  Plato’s Theory of Knowledge.
Heraclitus 1954. The Cosmic Fragments, edited by G.S. Kirk. Cambridge.
Hume, D. 1748. Enquiry concerning Human Understanding.
Kant, I. 1966. The Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Smith, N. K.
Keynes 1921. A Treatise on Probability. Macmillan.
Köhler, W. 1939. The Place of Value in a World of Facts. Kegen Paul.
Köhler, W. 1947. Gestalt Psychology. Liveright Co.
Langer, S.K.1942. Philosophy in a New Key. New American Library.
Lock, J. 1969. Essay on Human Understanding.
Mayor, R.G. 1951. Reason and Common Sense. Routledge and Kegan Paul Limited.
Moore, G.E. 1903. Principia Ethica.
Moore, G.E.1953. Some Main Problems of Philosophy. George Allen & Unwin.
Plato  Cratylus. H.N. Fowler’s translation.
Parmenides
Price, H.H. 1953. Thinking and Experience. Hutchinson's University Library.
Russell, B. 1912. The Problems of Philosophy.
Russell, B. Principia Mathematica.
Russell, B. An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth.
Russell, B. Human Knowledge.
Russell, B. The Analysis of Mind.
Russell, B. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy.
Russell, B. History of Western Philosophy.
Schrödinger, E. 1944. What Is Life?. Cambridge University Press.
Spearman, C. 1923. The Nature of Intelligence and the Principles of Cognition. Macmillan.
Strawson, P.F. 1952. Introduction to Logical Theory. Methuen.

Wittgenstein, L. 1922. Tractus Logico-Philosophicus., Kegan Paul.

Wittgenstein, L. 1963. Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Williams, L.P. 1965. Michael Faraday, Chapman and Hall.

2. Secondary References

[in English]
Denneson, T. J. 2007. “Wittgenstein on Seeing”.
Hawtrey, R., “Aspects”, read at the Friday Club about 1912, Hawtrey Papers 12/1, Churchill College, University of Cambridge.
Hawtrey, R., Good and Bad Trade: An Inquiry into the Causes of Trade Fluctuations, Constable & Company, 1913.
Hawtrey, R., Trade and Credit, Longmans, Green and Co., 1928.
Hawtrey, R. 1926. Economic Problem, Longmans, Green and Co.
Hawtrey, R. 1944. Economic Destiny, Longmans, Green and Co.
Hawtrey, R., Thought and Things, Hawtrey Papers, 12/1, Churchill College, University of Cambridge (unpublished).
Hawtrey, R., Right Policy: The Place of Value Judgements in Politics, Hawtrey Papers, 12/2, Churchill College, University of Cambridge (unpublished)
Heraclitus. 1954. The Cosmic Fragments, ed. By Kirk, G.S., Cambridge.
Hirai, T. 2012. Exploring Hawtrey's Social Philosophy through His Unpublished Book, Right Policy. Journal of the History of Economic Thought 34(2):169-192.
Keynes, J.M. 1921 (1973). A Treatise on Probability, Macmillan.
Keynes, J.M. 1926, Francis Ysidro Edgeworth 1845-1926, Economic Journal, March 1926.
Keynes, J.M. 1931. Ramsey as a Philosopher. The New Statesman and Nation.
Keynes, J.M. 1939. My Early Beliefs (in Two Memoirs, Rupert Hart-Davis, 1949).
Kurz, H. 2009. If Some People Looked Like Elephants and Others Like Cats, or Fish … (Review article of Brian McGuinness (ed.), Wittgenstein in Cambridge. Letters and Documents 1911-1951, Blackwell, 2008), European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 16-2: 361-374.
Ramsey, F. 1922. Mr Keynes on Probability. The Cambridge Magazine, January. Russell, B. 1912. The Problems of Philosophy. Williams and Norgate.
Russell, B. 1985. The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. Open Court Classics.
Shionoya, Y. 1992. Sidgwick, Moore and Keynes: a Philosophical Analysis of Keynes's 'My Early Beliefs' (in Bateman, B. and Davis, J. eds., Keynes and Philosophy, Edward Elgar. 6-29).
Shoroeder, S. 2010. A Tale of Two Problems: Wittgenstein's Discussion of Aspect Perception” (in J. Cottingham & P.M.S. Hacker (eds.), Mind, Method, and Morality: Essays in Honour of Anthony Kenny. Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Lee, D. ed. (T. Yamada, K. Chiba trans. 1996) Lectures by Wittgenstein I - Cambridge 1930-1932, Keiso Shobo.

[in Japanese]

Arahata, Y. 2013. “Constancy and Fragility – Wittgenstein and Heidegger” Reserch into European Culture, Seijo University, Vol.32, pp. 35-97. 
Itoh, K. 1999. Keynes’s Philosophy, Iwanami Shoten.
Kuroda, W. ed. 1978. Wittgenstein, Heibonsha.
Shimizu, I. 1972. Notes on Ethics, Iwanami Shoten.
Takiura, S. 1983. Wittgenstein, Iwanami Shoten.
Hirai, T. 2000. “Retrospective Reflections On My Early Beliefs” in T.Hirai, Keynes, Schumpeter, Hayek, Minerva Shobo (Ch.7. pp.169-186).
Hirai, T. 2002. Treatise on Probability and “My Early Beliefs”, History of Economic Thought, No.42.
Hirai, T. 2003. “Keynes as Philosopher and Keynes as Economist”, Sophia Economic Review, Vol.48, No. 12.                                                                  
Hirai, T. 2007. “Welfare and Value Hawtrey” in T. Hirai, Keynes and the Cambridge World, Minerva Shobo (Ch.5. pp.75-100).
Hirai, T. 2009. “Hawtrey On Unpublished Book, Right Policy” in T. Hirai ed. The Cambridge Development of the View of Market Society, Nihon Keizai Hyoronsha (pp.113-136).
Hirai, T. 2009. “The View of Market Society in Cambridge Survey” in T. Hirai ed. The Cambridge Development of the View of Market Society, Nihon Keizai Hyoronsha (pp.309-334).
Yonezawa, K. 2003. “What Kind of Meaning Did the Gestalt Psychology Have on the Development of Wittegenstein’s Philosophy?” Teikyo University Faculty of Literature (pp.211-253).